In my last post, I introduced the Möbius function , which is defined in terms of the prime factorization of
:
if
has any repeated prime factors, that is, if
is divisible by a perfect square.
- Otherwise, if
has
distinct prime factors,
. In other words,
if
has an even number of distinct prime factors, and
if the number of prime factors is odd.
Previously, we also considered the sum of all the primitive
th roots of unity. Today, we will begin proving they are the same:
for all
! This is surprising since it is not immediately obvious what the two functions have to do with each other: one is about sums of complex numbers, and the other is about prime factorization. On the other hand, perhaps it is not all that surprising after all: we’ve already seen that primitive roots of unity have a lot to do with divisibility and prime factorization. In any case, this connection is the key that cracks open a lot of really cool mathematics.
So, how will we do it? Recall that we proved satisfies this equation:
In the case of this was fairly “obvious”: we proved it essentially by staring at some pictures. But we will show that
also satisfies this equation, that is,
(In contrast to , this is not so obvious! But it’s true, and we will prove it.) Given a starting value for
, we have seen that this equation uniquely determines all values of a function for
: for example, given
, we can use the equation to uniquely determine
; given
and
, we can then uniquely determine
; and so on. So, if
and
both satisfy this equation, they must be the same for all
as long as they have the same starting value—and they do, since
.
I have to say that this is one of my favorite proofs—it rests on a beautiful little combinatorial argument, and, as we’ll see, it gives some insight into the Principle of Inclusion-Exclusion as well. We’ll start the proof today and then see the really beautiful part in my next post. So, without further ado:
Theorem.
Corollary. for all
.
Proof. Since , we can already see that
as desired. So now consider
for some
; we wish to show this sum is zero.
Since for values of
which are divisble by a perfect square, those values of
contribute nothing to the sum. We can therefore concentrate on only those
which are not divisible by a perfect square (we call such numbers squarefree). Each squarefree
must be a product of distinct prime factors, since if any prime factor was repeated, then
would be divisible by a perfect square. Since
, the prime factorization of each squarefree
is therefore a subset of the set of distinct prime factors of
, and conversely, each subset of the distinct prime factors of
yields a distinct squarefree divisor
.
For example, consider . Each squarefree divisor of
can have at most one copy of each of
,
, and
. There are therefore
squarefree divisors of
, one corresponding to each subset of
:
Adding up all the values of listed in the right column, we can see that there are four
’s and four
’s, which cancel to yield
as claimed.
As another example, for , all of the divisors of
are squarefree: we have
Our goal is to show that this sum is always zero, and the only way for it to be zero is if there are always an equal number of ’s and
’s. Given the definition of
, we know that the
’s come from even-sized subsets of the distinct prime factors of
, and the
’s come from odd-sized subsets. So in other words, we need to show that there are the same number of even-sized subsets as there are odd-sized subsets.
The fact that these are sets of distinct prime factors really makes no difference, since we are just counting them. What we really need, in essence, is the following lemma:
Subset parity lemma: any nonempty finite set has an equal number of even-sized and odd-sized subsets.
Can you see how to prove this? (And as an aside, do you see why it is false if we exclude the word “nonempty”? Do you see what this has to do with the versus
cases?) My next post will explain a nice proof of the lemma and then conclude the proof that
!
I do believe I see how to prove that. Hint:
Good! An extra challenge for you: can you prove it *without* using the Binomial Theorem?
I couldn’t do it in the 10 minutes I had available to think about it! Having said that, I do like Andrey’s proof (and presumably yours) below.
Here is my proof:
1. If n is odd then there is a simple bijection between even-sized e and odd-sized o subsets, achieved via set complement: e S\o.
2. If n > 0 is even then subsets that do not contain element n have the same bijection as in (1) above, while subsets that do contain n have a slightly different bijection: e S\o U {n}.
Nice, this is essentially the proof I had in mind, though I think your description for even sets not containing n may be slightly off: we don’t want to just take their set complement, but rather take the set complement and then remove n. Or did you have something different in mind?
Yes, you are right, I forgot to remove n after the complement in the first case.
P.S.: Apologies for messed up math formatting, I should have used LaTeX.
Pingback: The Möbius function proof, part 2 (the subset parity lemma) | The Math Less Traveled
Pingback: Dirichlet convolution and the Möbius function | The Math Less Traveled
Pingback: Möbius inversion | The Math Less Traveled